Note: Answers may be longer than I would deem sufficient on an exam. Some might vary slightly based on points of interest, examples, or personal experience. These suggested answers are designed to give you both the answer and a short explanation of why it is the answer.
Nash equilibrium is any outcome of a game where no player can improve their payoff by switching strategies, given the strategies of all other players. Another way to consider it is that all players are playing a strategy that is their best response to all other players’ strategies.
We can find Nash equilibrium several different ways:
All coordination games have two pure strategy Nash equilibria.
In the example above, both (Whitaker, Whitaker) and (Starbucks, Starbucks) are Nash equilibria, and no player has a strong preferences between one or the other outcomes.
In the example above, both (Whitaker, Whitaker) and (Starbucks, Starbucks) are Nash equilibria, but both players prefer (Whitaker, Whitaker).
In the example above, both (Hockey, Hockey) and (Ballet, Ballet) are Nash equilibria, but Harry prefers (Hockey, Hockey) and Sally prefers (Ballet, Ballet). 4. Chicken (or Hawk-Dove) features players that must choose between some “tough” strategy and a strategy where they “back down”. Each player prefers that they act tough and the other players back down. If both back down, nothing happens, whereas if they both act tough, they both suffer the worst consequence from a destructive conflict. The two Nash equilibria are where one player acts tough and the other acts cowardly. Since the equilibria are where each player chooses a different strategy, this is often considered an “anti-coordination game.”
In the example above, both (Tough, Back Down) and (Back Down, Tough) are Nash equilibria, but Player 1 prefers (Tough, Back Down) and Player 2 prefers (Back Down, Tough).
A focal point is a method of picking among alternative Nash equilibria in a coordination game. For players to achieve a good payout in a coordination game, their expectations of what each other will do need to converge on a common outcome. If there are multiple Nash equilibria, particularly if all are equally attractive, there may be no objective criterion on which to choose one for all players to coordinate around. However, there are often outcomes that, although apparently arbitrary and subjective, players “naturally” may converge on, due to cultural norms, beliefs, or “unwritten rules.” For example, when people are walking down a crowded path in both directions, they need to coordinate their behavior around a common rule to avoid bumping into each other. They can all keep left or all keep right, and neither outcome is particularly better than another, but we have common experience (at least in this country) since we drive on the right side of the road, that most people will end up keeping to the right.
An outcome is rationalizable if each player will play their particular strategy under some belief about what the other player is playing (i.e. if their chosen strategy is a best response to the strategy chosen by their opponent, and they believe that their opponent will play it).
We can eliminate some strategies as being not rationalizable if a strategy is never a best response to any opponents’ strategies.
A university is contemplating whether to build a new lab or a new theater on campus. The science faculty would rather see a new lab built, and the humanities faculty would prefer a new theater. However, the funding for the project (whichever it may turn out to be) is contingent on unanimous support from the faculty. If there is disagreement, neither project will go forward, leaving each group with no new building and their worst payoff. The meetings of the two separate faculty groups on which proposal to support occur simultaneously, with payoffs given in the following table:
The two pure strategy Nash equilibria are (Lab, ) and (Theater, ). They are underlined in the matrix above.
This is a Battle of the Sexes type coordination game, since there are two pure strategy Nash equilibria (each where both players play the same strategy), and each player prefers a different PSNE over the other.
Suppose it’s the early 2000’s and two Hollywood studios — Sony Pictures and Paramount Pictures — are each holding separate board meetings to strategize on how to keep up with the latest video technology. Two new advanced DVD standards are emerging on the market, HD-DVD and Blu Ray. Both firms would like to adopt a standard such that all other firms are using the same standard.
This is a pure coordination game. The two Nash equilibria are (HD-DVD, HD-DVD) and (Blue Ray, Blue Ray).
This is an assurance game. The two Nash equilibria are still (HD-DVD, HD-DVD) and (Blue Ray, Blue Ray), both firms prefer (HD-DVD, HD-DVD).
This is a Battle of the Sexes game. The two Nash equilibria are still (HD-DVD, HD-DVD) and (Blue Ray, Blue Ray), but Sony prefers (HD-DVD, HD-DVD) and Paramount prefers (Blue Ray, Blue Ray).
Management and labor for a major transportation company are renegotiating their collective bargaining agreement before the crucial holiday travel season. Both labor and management will benefit from reaching any agreement, and would both suffer if no deal is reached and the company goes out of business. Each party certaintly wants to gain the most concessions from the other. Each can bargain Hard and obtain maximal concessions from the other party, or bargain Soft and ask for minimal concessions. If both bargain Hard, it is impossible for them to reach a deal.
This is a Chicken/Hawk-Dove game. If one player bargains Hard and the other Soft, both gain something but the Hard bargainer gains more. If both play Soft, they benefit mildly, and if they both play Hard, neither benefits at all.
Both (Hard, Soft) and (Soft, Hard) are Nash equilibria, but Labor prefers (Hard, Soft) and Management prefers (Soft, Hard).
Find all Nash equilibria for the following games. First, check for dominant strategies. If there are none, solve using iterated elimination of dominant strategies. Describe your process (you can simply mark up the table, but describe what you are eliminating in what order, and why).
We are thus left with (Up, Right).
Given this, Rowena would play Down. We are thus left with (Down, Left).
Note if we had looked at Rowena, Straight weakly dominates Down, since she would be indifferent between them.
This leaves us with:
Given this, Rowena would play Straight. We are thus left with (Straight, Left).
From here, we are unable to eliminate any more strategies, since Rowena would be indifferent between playing Up or Straight in response to Middle.
There are thus two Nash equilibria: (Up, Middle) and (Straight, Middle)
Given this, Player 2 will play Right. This leaves us with the Nash equilibrium: (Down, Right, Right)
Solve the following games, for which there are no strictly dominated strategies. Describe your process (you can simply mark up the table).
I have underlined each player’s best response to the other player(s)’s strategies. Any outcome where all players are playing a best response is a Nash equilibrium.
Nash Equilibrium: (North, Right)
I have underlined each player’s best response to the other player(s)’s strategies. Any outcome where all players are playing a best response is a Nash equilibrium.
Nash Equilibria:
I have underlined each player’s best response to the other player(s)’s strategies. Any outcome where all players are playing a best response is a Nash equilibrium.
Nash Equilibrium: (Down, Right, Right)
Consider the following game:
The two Nash equilibria are (Middle, Middle) and (Down, Right).
(Middle, Middle) is the only Pareto efficient equilibrium, as it is a Pareto improvement from (Down, Right) as both players gain. But there are no possible improvements over (Middle, Middle).
(Middle, Middle) is where both players earn their highest payoff from the set of Nash equilibria.
(Down, Right) is risk dominant, since each player guarantees themselves a payoff of 50 if they play right, regardless of what the other player does.
Playing Middle is riskier, as it requires the other player to play Middle to attain the payoff dominant Nash equilibrium, otherwise a player might be stuck earning 0.
Which outcome(s) is/are rationalizable, and under what beliefs by each player?
We can go no further in eliminating strategies, since each remaining strategy for each player (Middle or Right) is a best response to some opposing strategy by the other player.
Hence, all four remaining outcomes are rationalizable under a certain set of beliefs by each player. Note that among these, only (Middle, Middle) and (Right, Right) are Nash equilibria!